Cape Argus E-dition

Unpacking euthanasia ethical dilemma

CHRIS JONES Jones is a chief researcher at the Department of Systematic Theology and Ecclesiology, and head of the Unit for Moral Leadership at Stellenbosch University

SEAN Davison, the euthanasia activist and co-founder of DignitySA, recently completed a sentence of house arrest in South Africa for his role in the deaths of three people. He said he had not committed a crime or murder, but had helped these people because they were desperate to die. Anrich Burger, Justin Varian and Richard Holland were suffering unbearably, with no hope of recovery and unable to end their own lives.

The late Archbishop Emeritus Desmond once wrote that he would want the option of an assisted death. Tutu argued that dying people should have the right to decide how and when they wanted to leave this life.

Legislation in Canada, and a number of US states and European countries, for example, allows assisted suicide. But there are still billions of people around the world, as in South Africa, who do not have this right.

The question of whether this is a legitimate right is a debate that has been raging for years in medical ethics and within religious groups.

This article is not about the religious or strictly legal aspects of the debate. It grapples with the ethical tension between arguments against and for active forms of euthanasia – one of the most contested ethical subjects in the world.

There are broadly three arguments against active forms of euthanasia:

● Only God has the authority to dispose over life and death;

● It is the role of medical doctors to preserve life, not to cause death;

● A doctor could abuse his or her position to take the lives of vulnerable patients, or patients might be killed against their wishes.

Although these arguments must be considered, I prefer to put forward the arguments in support of the active forms of euthanasia. But let’s first look, for the sake of clarity, at two forms of active euthanasia.

One is known as voluntary active euthanasia. This is when death is intentionally brought about in the life of a patient who is competent to make such a decision, and where death is reasonably believed to be in the interest of and based on an informed request by the patient. The doctor’s act is the proximate cause of death.

The second form of active euthanasia is where a doctor assists a patient in suicide, called “physician-assisted suicide”. The doctor intentionally provides the means to a competent individual, who then takes his or her own life. In South Africa, both these forms of euthanasia are illegal. In a constitutional democracy, active euthanasia should not be dealt with primarily as a theological issue. Of course, people of faith may express their beliefs about it, but they should not expect to dictate the law. There are many citizens who do not share religious values.

Although legislation in South Africa prohibits active forms of euthanasia, I believe that it is not against the Constitution. The Bill of Rights includes three relevant rights: ● Human dignity (article 10);

● Freedom and security of the person, including the right not to be treated or punished in a cruel, inhuman or degrading way (article 12(1));

● Bodily and psychological integrity, including the right to security in and control over one’s body (art 12(2)).

There is another point in favour of active euthanasia. The development of medical science means that people have more control over death and life than ever before. Although life has high value, it is not absolute.

People make decisions throughout their lives about their health. But when they are terminally ill, often in unbearable pain and suffering – and sometimes even losing their dignity – they are not allowed to decide when they want to die. If someone is terminally ill and suffers badly, can a strong moral case not be made that such a person – within prescribed medical-ethical parameters – be assisted with the dying process?

Three arguments have been put forward in support of active euthanasia:

● Personal autonomy should be respected. This implies that a competent person has a moral right to make his or her own choice;

● Unbearable suffering should be prevented. Nobody should be forced to endure suffering – often at high medical cost;

● When life is no longer good, and death is no longer bad, and when death is therefore preferred to continuing life, the role of medicine could change from healing and preserving life to helping someone die in a way that is compassionate, kind, gentle and respectful. For me, active forms of euthanasia are not so much the termination of life, but rather the shortening of suffering and the dying process.

OPINION

en-za

2022-07-01T07:00:00.0000000Z

2022-07-01T07:00:00.0000000Z

http://capeargus.pressreader.com/article/281749863047059

African News Agency